Why must we all work long hours to earn the right to live? Why must only the wealthy have access to leisure, aesÂthetÂic pleaÂsure, self-actuÂalÂizaÂtion…? EveryÂone seems to have an answer, accordÂing to their politÂiÂcal or theÂoÂlogÂiÂcal bent. One ecoÂnomÂic bogeyÂman, so-called “trickÂle-down” ecoÂnomÂics, or “Reaganomics,” actuÂalÂly preÂdates our 40th presÂiÂdent by a few hunÂdred years at least. The notion that we must betÂter ourselves—or simÂply survive—by toilÂing to increase the wealth and propÂerÂty of already wealthy men was perÂhaps first comÂpreÂhenÂsiveÂly articÂuÂlatÂed in the 18th-cenÂtuÂry docÂtrine of “improveÂment.” In order to jusÂtiÂfy priÂvaÂtizÂing comÂmon land and forcÂing the peasÂantry into jobÂbing for them, EngÂlish landÂlords attemptÂed to show in treaÂtise after treaÂtise that 1) the peasÂants were lazy, immoral, and unproÂducÂtive, and 2) they were betÂter off workÂing for othÂers. As a corolÂlary, most argued that landownÂers should be givÂen the utmost social and politÂiÂcal privÂiÂlege so that their largesse could benÂeÂfit everyÂone.
This scheme necesÂsiÂtatÂed a comÂplete redeÂfÂiÂnÂiÂtion of what it meant to work. In his study, The EngÂlish VilÂlage ComÂmuÂniÂty and the EncloÂsure MoveÂments, hisÂtoÂriÂan W.E. Tate quotes from sevÂerÂal of the “improveÂment” treaÂtisÂes, many writÂten by PuriÂtans who argued that “the poor are of two classÂes, the indusÂtriÂous poor who are conÂtent to work for their betÂters, and the idle poor who preÂfer to work for themÂselves.” Tate’s sumÂmaÂtion perÂfectÂly articÂuÂlates the earÂly modÂern redeÂfÂiÂnÂiÂtion of “work” as the creÂation of profÂit for ownÂers. Such work is virÂtuÂous, “indusÂtriÂous,” and leads to conÂtentÂment. OthÂer kinds of work, leisureÂly, domesÂtic, pleaÂsurÂable, subÂsisÂtence, or othÂerÂwise, qualifies—in an Orwellian turn of phrase—as “idleÂness.” (We hear echoes of this rhetoric in the lanÂguage of “deservÂing” and “undeÂservÂing” poor.) It was this lanÂguage, and its legal and social reperÂcusÂsions, that Max Weber latÂer docÂuÂmentÂed in The ProtesÂtant EthÂic and the SpirÂit of CapÂiÂtalÂism, Karl Marx reactÂed to in Das CapÂiÂtal, and femÂiÂnists have shown to be a conÂsolÂiÂdaÂtion of patriÂarÂchal powÂer and furÂther excluÂsion of women from ecoÂnomÂic parÂticÂiÂpaÂtion.
Along with Marx, varÂiÂous othÂers have raised sigÂnifÂiÂcant objecÂtions to ProtesÂtant, capÂiÂtalÂist defÂiÂnÂiÂtions of work, includÂing Thomas Paine, the FabiÂans, agrarÂiÂans, and anarÂchists. In the twenÂtiÂeth cenÂtuÂry, we can add two sigÂnifÂiÂcant names to an already disÂtinÂguished list of disÂsenters: BuckÂminÂster Fuller and Bertrand RusÂsell. Both chalÂlenged the notion that we must have wage-earnÂing jobs in order to live, and that we are not entiÂtled to indulge our pasÂsions and interÂests unless we do so for monÂeÂtary profÂit or have indeÂpenÂdent wealth. In a New York Times colÂumn on RusÂselÂl’s 1932 essay “In Praise of IdleÂness,” Gary GutÂting writes, “For most of us, a payÂing job is still utterÂly essenÂtial — as massÂes of unemÂployed peoÂple know all too well. But in our ecoÂnomÂic sysÂtem, most of us inevitably see our work as a means to someÂthing else: it makes a livÂing, but it doesn’t make a life.”
In far too many casÂes in fact, the work we must do to surÂvive robs us of the abilÂiÂty to live by ruinÂing our health, conÂsumÂing all our preÂcious time, and degradÂing our enviÂronÂment. In his essay, RusÂsell argued that “there is far too much work done in the world, that immense harm is caused by the belief that work is virÂtuÂous, and that what needs to be preached in modÂern indusÂtriÂal counÂtries is quite difÂferÂent from what has always been preached.” His “arguÂments for laziÂness,” as he called them, begin with defÂiÂnÂiÂtions of what we mean by “work,” which might be charÂacÂterÂized as the difÂferÂence between labor and manÂageÂment:
What is work? Work is of two kinds: first, alterÂing the posiÂtion of matÂter at or near the earth’s surÂface relÂaÂtiveÂly to othÂer such matÂter; secÂond, telling othÂer peoÂple to do so. The first kind is unpleasÂant and ill paid; the secÂond is pleasÂant and highÂly paid.
RusÂsell furÂther divides the secÂond catÂeÂgoÂry into “those who give orders” and “those who give advice as to what orders should be givÂen.” This latÂter kind of work, he says, “is called polÂiÂtics,” and requires no real “knowlÂedge of the subÂjects as to which advice is givÂen,” but only the abilÂiÂty to manipÂuÂlate: “the art of perÂsuaÂsive speakÂing and writÂing, i.e. of adverÂtisÂing.” RusÂsell then disÂcussÂes a “third class of men” at the top, “more respectÂed than either of the classÂes of the workers”—the landownÂers, who “are able to make othÂers pay for the privÂiÂlege of being allowed to exist and to work.” The idleÂness of landownÂers, he writes, “is only renÂdered posÂsiÂble by the indusÂtry of othÂers. Indeed their desire for comÂfortÂable idleÂness is hisÂtorÂiÂcalÂly the source of the whole gospel of work. The last thing they have ever wished is that othÂers should folÂlow their examÂple.”
The “gospel of work” RusÂsell outÂlines is, he writes, “the moralÂiÂty of the Slave State,” and the kinds of murÂderÂous toil that develÂoped under its rule—actual chatÂtel slavÂery, fifÂteen hour workÂdays in abomÂinable conÂdiÂtions, child labor—has been “disÂasÂtrous.” Work looks very difÂferÂent today than it did even in RusÂselÂl’s time, but even in moderÂniÂty, when labor moveÂments have manÂaged to gathÂer some increasÂingÂly preÂcarÂiÂous amount of social secuÂriÂty and leisure time for workÂing peoÂple, the amount of work forced upon the majorÂiÂty of us is unnecÂesÂsary for human thrivÂing and in fact counter to it—the result of a still-sucÂcessÂful capÂiÂtalÂist proÂpaÂganÂda camÂpaign: if we aren’t laborÂing for wages to increase the profÂits of othÂers, the logÂic still dicÂtates, we will fall to sloth and vice and fail to earn our keep. “Satan finds some misÂchief for idle hands to do,” goes the ProtesÂtant proverb RusÂsell quotes at the beginÂning of his essay. On the conÂtrary, he conÂcludes,
…in a world where no one is comÂpelled to work more than four hours a day, every perÂson posÂsessed of sciÂenÂtifÂic curiosÂiÂty will be able to indulge it, and every painter will be able to paint withÂout starvÂing, howÂevÂer excelÂlent his picÂtures may be. Young writÂers will not be obligÂed to draw attenÂtion to themÂselves by senÂsaÂtionÂal pot-boilÂers, with a view to acquirÂing the ecoÂnomÂic indeÂpenÂdence for monÂuÂmenÂtal works, for which, when the time at last comes, they will have lost the taste and capacÂiÂty.
The less we are forced to labor, the more we can do good work in our idleÂness, and we can all labor less, RusÂsell argues, because “modÂern methÂods of proÂducÂtion have givÂen us the posÂsiÂbilÂiÂty of ease and secuÂriÂty for all” instead of “overÂwork for some and starÂvaÂtion for othÂers.”
A few decades latÂer, visionÂary archiÂtect, invenÂtor, and theÂoÂrist BuckÂminÂster Fuller would make exactÂly the same arguÂment, in simÂiÂlar terms, against the “speÂcious notion that everyÂbody has to earn a livÂing.” Fuller articÂuÂlatÂed his ideas on work and non-work throughÂout his long career. He put them most sucÂcinctÂly in a 1970 New York magÂaÂzine “EnviÂronÂmenÂtal Teach-In”:
It is a fact today that one in ten thouÂsand of us can make a techÂnoÂlogÂiÂcal breakÂthrough capaÂble of supÂportÂing all the rest…. We keep inventÂing jobs because of this false idea that everyÂbody has to be employed at some kind of drudgery because, accordÂing to MalthuÂsian-DarÂwinÂian theÂoÂry, he must jusÂtiÂfy his right to exist.
Many peoÂple are paid very litÂtle to do backÂbreakÂing labor; many othÂers paid quite a lot to do very litÂtle. The creÂation of surÂplus jobs leads to redunÂdanÂcy, inefÂfiÂcienÂcy, and the bureauÂcratÂic waste we hear so many politiÂcians rail against: “we have inspecÂtors and peoÂple makÂing instruÂments for inspecÂtors to inspect inspectors”—all to satÂisÂfy a dubiÂous moral imperÂaÂtive and to make a small numÂber of rich peoÂple even richÂer.
What should we do instead? We should conÂtinÂue our eduÂcaÂtion, and do what we please, Fuller argues: “The true busiÂness of peoÂple should be to go back to school and think about whatÂevÂer it was they were thinkÂing about before someÂbody came along and told them they had to earn a livÂing.” We should all, in othÂer words, work for ourÂselves, perÂformÂing the kind of labor we deem necÂesÂsary for our qualÂiÂty of life and our social arrangeÂments, rather than the kinds of labor dicÂtatÂed to us by govÂernÂments, landownÂers, and corÂpoÂrate execÂuÂtives. And we can all do so, Fuller thought, and all flourÂish simÂiÂlarÂly. Fuller called the techÂnoÂlogÂiÂcal and evoÂluÂtionÂary advanceÂment that enables us to do more with less “eupheÂmerÂalÂizaÂtion.” In CritÂiÂcal Path, a visionÂary work on human develÂopÂment, he claimed “It is now posÂsiÂble to give every man, woman and child on Earth a stanÂdard of livÂing comÂpaÂraÂble to that of a modÂern-day bilÂlionÂaire.”
Sound utopiÂan? PerÂhaps. But Fuller’s far-reachÂing path out of reliance on fosÂsil fuels and into a susÂtainÂable future has nevÂer been tried, for some depressÂingÂly obviÂous reaÂsons and some less obviÂous. NeiÂther RusÂsell nor Fuller argued for the abolition—or inevitable self-destruction—of capÂiÂtalÂism and the rise of a workÂers’ parÂadise. (RusÂsell gave up his earÂly enthuÂsiÂasm for comÂmuÂnism.) NeiÂther does Gary GutÂting, a phiÂlosÂoÂphy proÂfesÂsor at the UniÂverÂsiÂty of Notre Dame, who in his New York Times comÂmenÂtary on RusÂsell asserts that “CapÂiÂtalÂism, with its devoÂtion to profÂit, is not in itself evil.” Most MarxÂists on the othÂer hand would argue that devoÂtion to profÂit can nevÂer be benign. But there are many midÂdle ways between state comÂmuÂnism and our curÂrent reliÂgious devoÂtion to supÂply-side capÂiÂtalÂism, such as robust demoÂcÂraÂtÂic socialÂism or a basic income guarÂanÂtee. In any case, what most disÂsenters against modÂern notions of work share in comÂmon is the conÂvicÂtion that eduÂcaÂtion should proÂduce critÂiÂcal thinkers and self-directÂed indiÂvidÂuÂals, and not, as GutÂting puts it, “be priÂmarÂiÂly for trainÂing workÂers or consumers”—and that doing work we love for the sake of our own perÂsonÂal fulÂfillÂment should not be the excluÂsive preÂserve of a propÂerÂtied leisure class.
RelatÂed ConÂtent:
Charles BukowsÂki Rails Against 9‑to‑5 Jobs in a BruÂtalÂly HonÂest LetÂter (1986)
Josh Jones is a writer and musiÂcian based in Durham, NC. FolÂlow him at @jdmagness